Key Takeaway:

Stanford neurobiologist Robert Sapolsky’s book, Determined: A Science of Life Without Free Will, has been criticized for arguing that free will is an illusion. Determinism, the idea that we are causally determined to act as we do due to our histories, is a radical position that only 11% of philosophers agree with. However, compatibilists believe humans are agents who act for moral reasons and have a certain type of freedom. They argue that being constrained by determinism isn’t the same as being constrained to a chair by a rope. Incompatibilists argue that having alternatives or being “undetermined” isn’t what undermines free will, and free will is something else entirely. Sapolsky needs to show why his assumptions about what counts as free will are relevant to moral responsibility. The point of this debate is not to show compatibilists are right, but to highlight the nuanced debate surrounding free will and moral responsibility.


Itย seemsย like we have free will.

However, the latest book by Stanford neurobiologist Robert Sapolsky, Determined: A Science of Life Without Free Will, has been receiving a lot ofmedia attention for arguing science shows this is an illusion.

Sapolskyโ€™s book was published in October 2023. Wikimedia

Sapolsky summarises the latest scientific research relevant to determinism: the idea that weโ€™re causally โ€œdeterminedโ€ to act as we do because of our histories โ€“ and couldnโ€™t possibly act any other way.

According to determinism, just as a rock that is dropped is determined to fall due to gravity, your neurons are determined to fire a certain way as a direct result of your environment, upbringing, hormones, genes, culture and myriad other factors outside your control. And this is true regardless of how โ€œfreeโ€ your choices seem to you.ย 

Sapolsky also says that because our behaviour is determined in this way, nobody is morally responsible for what they do. He believes while we can lock up murderers to keep others safe, they technically donโ€™t deserve to be punished.

This is quite a radical position. Itโ€™s worth asking why only 11% of philosophers agree with Sapolsky, compared with the 60% who think being causally determined is compatible with having free will and being morally responsible.

Have these โ€œcompatibilistsโ€ failed to understand the science? Or has Sapolsky failed to understand free will?

Is determinism incompatible with free will?

โ€œFree willโ€ and โ€œresponsibilityโ€ can mean a variety of different things depending on how you approach them.

Many people think of free will as having the ability to choose between alternatives. Determinism might seem to threaten this, because if we are causally determined then we lack any real choice between alternatives; we only ever make the choice we were always going to make.

But there are counterexamples to this way of thinking. For instance, suppose when you started reading this article someone secretly locked your door for 10 seconds, preventing you from leaving the room during that time. You, however, had no desire to leave anyway because you wanted to keep reading โ€“ so you stayed where you are. Was your choice free?

Many would argue even though you lacked the option to leave the room, this didnโ€™t make your choice to stay unfree. Therefore, lacking alternatives isnโ€™t what decides whether you lack free will. What matters instead is how the decision came about.

The trouble with Sapolskyโ€™s arguments, as free will expert John Martin Fischer explains, is he doesnโ€™t actually present any argument for why his conception of free will is correct. 

He simply defines free will as being incompatible with determinism, assumes this absolves people of moral responsibility, and spends much of the book describing the many ways our behaviours are determined. His arguments can all be traced back to his definition of โ€œfree willโ€.

Compatibilists believe humans are agents. We live lives with โ€œmeaningโ€, have an understanding of right and wrong, and act for moral reasons. This is enough to suggest most of us, most of the time, have a certain type of freedom and are responsible for our actions (and deserving of blame) โ€“ even if our behaviours are โ€œdeterminedโ€. 

Compatibilists would point out that being constrained by determinism isnโ€™t the same as being constrained to a chair by a rope. Failing to save a drowning child because you were tied up is not the same as failing to save a drowning child because you were โ€œdeterminedโ€ not to care about them. The former is an excuse. The latter is cause for condemnation.

Incompatibilists must defend themselves better

Some readers sympathetic to Sapolsky might feel unconvinced. They might say your decision to stay in the room, or ignore the child, was still caused by influences in your history that you didnโ€™t control โ€“ and therefore you werenโ€™t truly free to choose.

However, this doesnโ€™t prove that having alternatives or being โ€œundeterminedโ€ is the only way we can count as having free will. Instead, it assumes they are. From the compatibilistsโ€™ point of view, this is cheating. 

A path in a forest splits off to both sides.
Compatibilists believe humans are agents who act for moral reasons. Shutterstock

Compatibilists and incompatibilists both agree that, given determinism is true, there is a sense in which you lack alternatives and could not do otherwise.

However, incompatibilists will say you therefore lack free will, whereas compatibilists will say you still possess free will because that sense of โ€œlacking alternativesโ€ isnโ€™t what undermines free will โ€“ and free will is something else entirely. 

They say as long as your actions came from you in a relevant way (even if โ€œyouโ€ were โ€œdeterminedโ€ by other things), you count as having free will. When youโ€™re tied up by a rope, the decision to not save the drowning child doesnโ€™t come from you. But when you just donโ€™t care about the child, it does.

By another analogy, if a tree falls in a forest and nobody is around, one person may say no auditory senses are present, so this is incompatible with sound existing. But another person may say even though no auditory senses are present, this is still compatible with sound existing because โ€œsoundโ€ isnโ€™t about auditory perception โ€“ itโ€™s about vibrating atoms.

Both agree nothing is heard, but disagree on what factors are relevant to determining the existence of โ€œsoundโ€ in the first place. Sapolsky needs to show why his assumptions about what counts as free will are the ones relevant to moral responsibility. As philosopher Daniel Dennett once put it, we need to ask which โ€œvarieties of free will [are] worth wantingโ€.

Free will isnโ€™t a scientific question

The point of this back and forth isnโ€™t to show compatibilists are right. It is to highlight thereโ€™s a nuanced debate to engage with. Free will is a thorny issue. Showing nobody is responsible for what they do requires understanding and engaging with all the positions on offer. Sapolsky doesnโ€™t do this.

Sapolskyโ€™s broader mistake seems to be assuming his questions are purely scientific: answered by looking just at what the science says. While science is relevant, we first need some idea of what free will is (which is a metaphysical question) and how it relates to moral responsibility (a normative question). This is something philosophers have been interrogating for a very long time.

Interdisciplinary work is valuable and scientists are welcome to contribute to age-old philosophical questions. But unless they engage with existing arguments first, rather than picking a definition they like and attacking others for not meeting it, their claims will simply be confused.

Contributor

Recently Published

Key Takeaway: NASA’s Curiosity and Perseverance rover missions are investigating the planet’s evidence for life, known as its “biosignatures,” in unprecedented detail. The rovers are acting as extraterrestrial detectives, hunting for clues that life may have existed eons ago, including evidence of long-gone liquid surface water, life-sustaining minerals, and organic molecules. The Mars of today […]
Key Takeaway: Jonathan Haidt’s book, The Anxious Generation, calls for action to limit teenagers’ smartphone access and address the mental health crisis caused by the widespread use of smartphones. Haidt cites the “great rewiring” period from 2010 to 2015 as a time when adolescents’ neural systems were primed for anxiety and depression by daily smartphone […]

Top Picks

Key Takeaway: A project involving archaeologists, astronomers, and photographers from English Heritage, Oxford, Leicester, and Bournemouth universities, as well as the Royal Astronomical Society, aims to study the lunar alignment at Stonehenge. The project aims to identify the layout of certain stones and the major lunar standstill, which occurs when the northernmost and southernmost moonrises […]
Key Takeaway: A study has found that humble leaders can become more promotable by growing others through a “humility route”. Human capital theory suggests that employees’ value can be enhanced by investing in their knowledge, skills, and abilities. Humble leaders focus on the learning and growth of their followers, creating human capital value for themselves. […]

Trending

I highly recommend reading the McKinsey Global Instituteโ€™s new report, โ€œReskilling China: Transforming The Worldโ€™s Largest Workforce Into Lifelong Learnersโ€, which focuses on the countryโ€™s biggest employment challenge, re-training its workforce and the adoption of practices such as lifelong learning to address the growing digital transformation of its productive fabric. How to transform the country […]

Join our Newsletter

Get our monthly recap with the latest news, articles and resources.

Login

Welcome to Empirics

We are glad you have decided to join our mission of gathering the collective knowledge of Asia!
Join Empirics